ALTRUISM: BEING SELFLESS FOR THE THE WELL-BEING OF THE OTHER
ALTRUISM:
BEING SELFLESS FOR THE THE WELL-BEING OF THE OTHER
1.0 Introduction
Thinking is always a rational progression that
tries to solve the glitches of the world with renewed intelligence and
comprehension. It includes a makeover not only in rationality but also in
action. Altruism is one of the rational requirements of action. What is the
role of the philosophy of altruism in human life? To answer this question, it
is necessary first to know whether altruism a desire to benefit someone else
for his or her sake rather than one’s own, even exists in humans. The reality
of the philosophy of altruism has been debated, often vehemently, for
centuries. The reason for the frenzied debate is that if altruism occurs, it
has philosophical inferences. The certainty and existence of altruism point our
energy towards the fundamental human nature; do all actions of humanity focused
on benefiting ourselves? Those who carefully
consider the human state often accomplish that self-interest triggers all our
deeds. Even though we are self-interested beings, altruism does exist in
humans. Since altruism holds a complex nature, we need a combined approach to
understand it better. What I do in this first chapter is to present altruism as
a philosophy of being selfless for the well-being of the other. My effort in
this chapter is to discuss definitions of the philosophy of altruism, its
developments, the role of philosophy of altruism in the human life, the rationale of the philosophy of altruism and ethos in
the evolution of altruistic thought patterns, traditional philosophical
thoughts of altruism, the religious outlook of the philosophy of altruism,
motives of the philosophy of altruism, the necessity of Supererogation, reciprocity,
and impartiality in the philosophy of altruism, etc.
1.1 What do we understand by the philosophy of altruism?
The French term ‘altruisme’
was coined by Auguste Comte in his Système
de Politique Positive in 1851.[1] It
combined the Latin alter with ui and literally meant ‘to this other’.
The English ‘altruism’ was first introduced into Britain by George H. Lewes, a
popularizer of Comte’s work, in 1853. When Comte explained his theories of
phrenology in System of Positive Politics
I, he presented the cerebral table by looking at the natural basis of the
true general theory of affective life.[2] Auguste Comte then describes the structure and meaning of his table.
According to him, there is a threefold division – a very general feature of
Comte’s thought – between the heart (the loving part of the human being), the
mind (the thinking part) and the character (the active part).[3] The altruism versus egoism conflict is located in the loving dimension,
in which Comte distinguishes no less than ten instincts.[4] The altruistic instincts are the
last of the three instincts and they have placed in the middle of the forefront
of the brain: kindness first, followed by veneration, while attachment links
with egoistic instincts.[5]
Even though altruism is “elimination of selfish desire and egocentrism, as well
as leading a life devoted to the well-being of others”[6], Comte does not nurse egoism and
altruism as two drastically contrasting instincts and tried to blend egoism and altruism with the two intermediary
tendencies: “between the direct interest of the isolated individual and true
social feeling there exists an indirect interest, which is still individual but
which brings each individual into relation with the other in order to obtain
individual satisfaction.”[7] The action would only be called altruistic if it was done with
the conscious intention of helping another which is contrary to self-interested
or selfish or egoistic.[8]
Herbert Spencer too had given importance to altruism and for him, the
family is a congenial context for altruistic behavior. Spencer considered
altruism to be an exact form of action and not an instinct; this is clear in
his definition of altruism as “all action which, in the normal course of
things, benefits others, instead of benefiting self”.[9] He developed a non-conscious form of altruism. [10] He construed in terms of the
means-end relations. Spencer apprehended
an evolutionary interpretation of the growth of altruism, instead of the
historical approach of Comte. Spencer appears to follow a meta-historical approach
to the rise of altruism: from unconscious to conscious altruism in the family,
from familial altruism to social altruism.[11] When he spoke of the cooperation, he developed four-stage birth of
altruism[12] and the final stage of it is “characterized by an increase of sympathy
leading to exchange of services beyond agreement”.[13] He explained these four stages
in terms of the calculus of pain and pleasure and of the way how egoists and
altruists made a selection to fit their social context. Spencer rules out
Comte’s motto live for others and this statement itself is as same as an
egoistic motto. He did not accept the
Comte’s claim that truly social life means to live for others, objective
behaviors and feelings paving the way for subjective immortality given by the
life in others, that is to say, those who will remain in their memory a
recollection of the objective life of members of past generations.[14] According to Spencer, egoism is the beginning stage of altruism.[15] Altruism and egoism were treated
as if they were behaviors on the same continuum through cooperation and
compromise, in sharp contrast to Comte, who considered altruism to be an
instinct and a value different from egoism, and who distinguished egoistic altruism
from pure altruism. Their thoughts underline the idea that altruism is a
rational determination to give the other.
Many other thinkers have cherished the benevolence to define altruism.
For Thomas Nagel, altruism is the inclination to act for the welfares of the
other.[16] Stephen Post sees altruism as unselfish delight and unlimited love in
the comfort of others.[17] Daniel Batson felt altruism as an action with the motive of the
happiness of the needy.[18] This sense of altruism has the taste of the agape of
Christianity, Maitri, and Karuna of Buddhism, parasahayam
of Hinduism. Not only action but also motivation also is the defining factor of
altruism. It is an action looking forward to the well being of others at the
jeopardy of ourselves without imagining any returns from others.[19] The motivation behind each action seems like an inspiration. Here I do
not take into consideration certain undesirable
and unforeseen consequences. A hindrance
to taking action, which goes out of the control of the one who wills to act
does not at all diminish the altruistic nature of his motivation. Taking risks
for the good for the accomplishment of the goodness of the other is a necessary
sufficient factor to qualify as altruistic behavior.[20] Here one acts out of benevolence and not out of personal gains. There
are mainly two mechanisms to altruism; give worth to others and have a concern
about the circumstances of others’ life.[21] When we human beings hold these two in our heart, we generate
benevolence and sympathy with broadmindedness and willingness to help the needy
for their well being to limit the sufferings of the suffered. If one fails to
grant worthiness to others, one will be
indifferent to the needs of the needy.
Without valuing the other, no one can be altruistic.
Human beings’ certain intellectual status and long-lasting temperaments make
an effect on altruism. Baston visualizes altruism as a momentary mental state
lined to the perception of a particular need in another person, rather than as
a lasting disposition.[22] He talks more of the philosophy of altruism than the altruists because
an intellectual conflict emerges while one acts because of the mixture of
motivations one holds as selfish or altruistic. It appears then sincere to
speak also of altruistic or selfish temperaments according to the cerebral states
that usually outweigh in a person all the phases between categorical altruism
and narrow-minded selfishness.[23] The Scottish philosopher Francis Hutcheson said about altruism that it
should not be an action arise out of compassion or gratitude, it should be fixed
humanity to the others whom our influence can extend.[24] We tend to define goodness as a principle or dogma but it is more than
that, a way of existing or living. Together with the certain internal
dispositions, altruists do have a special way of seeing the things of the world.
“Altruists simply have a different way of seeing things. Where the rest of us
see a stranger, altruists see a fellow human being. While many disparate
factors may contribute to the existence and development if what I identify as
an altruistic perspective, it is the perspective itself that constitutes the
heart of altruism”.[25] Our spur-of-the-moment responses tackled with unanticipated
surroundings reproduce our deep-set dispositions and our grade of interior
readiness.[26] We cannot reject the fact that altruism infuses our observances. It is
articulated promptly when we are antagonized with the requirements of the
other. Today moral philosophical way gives the only emphasis to what is right
giving the least importance to the nature of valuable life. These views open
our horizons to see it from a wider perspective and to cultivate altruism as a
way of being of our lives. Historical understanding of the development of
altruism will deepen our knowledge of altruism.
1.2 Glimpse of the philosophy of altruism: the beginning and its
historical developments
The philosophy of altruism is a philosophy of other-centered love and
concern with selfless motives. The comprehensive overview of the history of the
philosophy of altruism is vital to do better something for the other in the
world today.
1.2.1 Philosophy of altruism in the ancient philosophical perspectives
and sacred stance
To understand the real meaning of altruism we have to
understand the meaning of altruism in ancient philosophy and early traditions.
Philosophy of altruism and morality can be called as the two sides of the same
coin.[27]
The basic moral questions began to be questioned from the ancient philosophies
of Plato and Aristotle.[28]
When Aristotle makes a discussion on friendship in his Nichomachean Ethics, there we see a glimpse of altruism. Aristotle describes friendship as
reciprocated goodwill, mainly a relationship between two people in which love
and goodwill are shared where one wishes always for the goodness of one’s friend
for their sake. [29] In the viewpoint of Aristotle, virtuous men
always wish and have a tendency to act for the wellness of the other.[30] Here always emerge certain questions regarding
our ends behind each moral act; whether it is for self or the other. In his philosophy,
we humans sometimes seek the goodness of friends and other times goodness of oneself.
Self-centered behavior of oneself is named as an attribute of the bad human
being.[31] But things are not so simple, because in acting in a way that is motivated
by the interests of one’s friend is in a way that he is acting both for the
friend’s sake and by an extension of one’s feeling, for oneself. In one way or
in another way each one is in friendship with oneself and he spoke the
difference between the self and others
too, which is central to the moral philosophy today. Aristotle’s opinion was that friends hold a mirror up to each
other; through that mirror, they can see each other in ways that would not
otherwise be accessible to them, and it is this reciprocal mirroring that helps
them improve themselves as persons.[32] Friends, then, share a similar concept of eudaimonia and help each
other achieve it. But he did not tell
anything of one’s obligation towards the stranger. He just
preferred true friendship as the best way to give services to others. When he illustrated the self-love, he
sketched the discrepancies between self-love that is worthy and self-love that
which promotes only self-gratification of oneself as unvirtuous.[33] When one acts for the betterment of one’s friend, he
acquires virtuousness nature becomes a progressed human being.[34] Since altruism is always in concern of the centrality
of self, always question emerges whether it is possible to act only for the
welfare of the other. Concerning this question, Aristotle answers in his Eudemian Ethics; it is true to say of the man of good character that
he performs many actions for the sake of his friends and his country and if
necessary even dies for them. For he will sacrifice both money and honors and in
general the goods that people struggle to obtain in pursuit of what is morally
fine.[35] But here we can see that mere virtuous (altruistic)
action doesn’t give any good to the friends. “Virtuous action is a rational
moral action in pursuit of that which in addition to the good it does its
beneficiaries (one’s friends), is also morally fine”.[36] Motives have a prior role in the philosophy of
altruism.
The concept of the
other was very familiar in the moral traditions of Judaism and Christianity. Their dictum was ‘love your neighbor’ and it
was an approach against selfishness and self-love (ego). In the Old
Testament, we see a command against revenge, ‘love your neighbor as
thyself’[37]; a commandment
against coveting the property of the neighbor, ‘by coveting the properties of
the neighbors, don’t give any false witness to our neighbors’.[38] Even the good
manners of one to the other and necessity of the reciprocity are very well
explained in Golden Rule which has its root in Talmud; “a certain
heathen came to Shammai and said to him: ‘Make me a proselyte, on condition
that you teach me the whole Torah while I stand on one foot’. Thereupon he
repulsed him with the rod, which was in his hand. When he went to Hillel, he
said to him, ‘what is hateful to you do not do to your neighbor: that is the
whole Torah; all the rest of it is
commentary; go and learn”.[39] The Golden Rule says; “do unto others as you
would have them do unto you”[40]. Another version
of it can be seen as follows; “love one
another as I have loved you. No one has greater love than this than to lay down
one’s life for one’s friends”.[41] As we have seen
in Aristotle, here there is an ultimate presentation of love in our actions
towards the other. Altruistic acts in the Christian and Judeo tradition can be
called as the expression of the love to God. The scripture provides divine
paraphernalia to the philosophy of altruism. This type of approach is seen not only
in Catholic and Judeo traditions but also in Hinduism, Islamic traditions, Buddhist traditions,
Jainism principles, etc. In Mahābhārata, we read the advice of Vidura to
the King Yuddhiśhṭhira;
Listening to wise scriptures, austerity,
sacrifice, respectful faith, social welfare, forgiveness, purity of intent,
compassion, truth, and self-control—are the ten wealth of character (self). O
king aim for these, may you be steadfast in these qualities. These are the
basis of prosperity and rightful living. These are the highest attainable
things. All worlds are balanced on dharma, dharma encompasses
ways to prosperity as well. O King, dharma is the best quality
to have, wealth the medium and desire (kāma) the lowest. Hence, (keeping
these in mind), by self-control and by making dharma (right
conduct) your main focus, treat others as you treat yourself.[42]
In
Islamic teachings,
especially in Hadith,[43] we read as follows; “A Bedouin came to the
prophet, grabbed the stirrup of his camel and said: O the messenger of God!
Teach me something to go to heaven with it. Prophet said: As you would have
people do to you, do to them; and what you dislike to be done to you, don't do
to them. Now let the stirrup go. This
maxim is enough for you; go and act in accordance with it”.[44] Buddhists and Jainists ahimsa and karma
also have the same indications.[45] They
always forbid harmless to all living beings as part of the prohibition of
causing living beings to suffer, these religions exhort us to treat others with
respect and compassion. In this positive and direct form of Golden Rule, we can
say, it tells us to consider others as others one would like to be considered.
In its negative and prohibitive for, one should not try to have conducted in
the ways one would not like to be treated. In its emphatic and responsive form,
we can say, what you wish upon others, you wish upon yourself too. Therefore we
say, the shortest way to benevolence is Golden Rule.
The elegant scholastic philosopher Thomas Aquinas
excavated the virtuous concepts of ethics of Aristotle and added courage to the
Christian principles of charity to be virtuous and to be happy.[46] Thomas Aquinas understands you should love
your neighbor as yourself with the connotation that love for ourselves is the
exemplar of love for others. Considering that the love with which a man
loves himself in the form and root of friendship and quotes Aristotle that the
origin of friendly relations with others lies in our relations to
ourselves, he concluded that we are not bound to love others more than
ourselves, but more than the private good we have to look for the public good.[47] The ultimate end of human life for
Aquinas is eternal beatitude. There is no virtue without charity for Aquinas.
He also had discussed the question of whether to do an act that endangers
one’’s values. For him, the spontaneous is not praiseworthy. When there is a
risk in doing more good, it's more virtuous. “The
elements of risk and danger in virtuous action are components of that certain
kind of altruistic action that is defined by sacrifice or by the need for the
agent to give something up in performing the act. This action is, for Aquinas,
directed ultimately towards the end of achieving divinity”.[48] The love of charity leads to God. Holy Spirit as the eternal power will
give powers to all risks and fears of doing. But the motivation of all these
acts is nothing but blissfulness or divinity.[49] In its motivational point of view, it may be criticized because
Christianity does not understand altruism in the same way as we understand
altruism today in its point. The highest motivational point of the philosophy
of altruism is the well-being of the other or needy while the motivation of
Christianity is the eternal reward.
1.2.2. Critical outline to Thomas Hobbes’ philosophy
of altruism
Thomas Hobbes’ ethics was a moral gesture positioned on other-centered
behavior because of human nature. The
presence of natural law as in Aquinas’ principles and scholastic school is
crystal clear even in the philosophical ethics of Thomas Hobbes. All his
philosophical principles had its roots in reason and intellect. For him, there is nothing in the human mind that does
not originally derive from sensory perception and which is not caused by
material stimuli from the outside world.[50] He considers the human mind
itself as part of the material world, and not as something of a radically
different substance.
Human beings are egoist beings and in the world, there are not
transcendent normative orders. We, human beings have tried their level best to
make their order to fulfill their psychological and biological natures. Since
human beings are self-interested beings, their actions are motivated by the
self-interestedness to fulfill their desires and end to necessity and survival.[51] For him, the nature of human beings is individualistic and they are
originally free and equal with philosophers of natural law.[52] Since he held the notion of natural law, he believed in the freedom and
supremacy of personal interests over the others’ interests too. For him, since
there is no eternal and universally valid standard of good evil, one has to
rationalize the personal inclinations of good and evil. Since the freedom of
human beings has a chance for exploitation and competition, he proposed
subjective preferences to recognize common interests through means-end
reasoning. For him, all these things are for one’s security. Even when he outlined
the lists of the law of nature, even the golden rule was placed as last of it.[53] His intention behind proposing
all these only to defend one’s own interests. His expression goes like this; ‘do, not that to another, which thou thinking unreasonable to
be done by another to thy self’.[54] For him, to secure one’s interests are prior to
interests for the other. Catholic golden rule is altruistic while Hume’s golden
principles are altruistic. Since Hume gives prior concern for the protection of
one’s own interests, his views are egoistic. We deduct it from his definition
of the law of nature. The Law of nature is a rule according to which a person
is forbidden to do anything that is self-destructive or removes their ability
to preserve their own life.[55] Hume expresses ‘do not that to another’ while the
Bible expresses ‘do unto others’.His understanding of the golden rule is merely
for one’s survival or only to fulfill one’s ends. We can’t call golden rule as
altruistic because it underlines only the mutual ethical necessity, nothing
more than that. Many philosophers criticized Hume’s egoism because of its
diversion from the Christian tradition.
1.2.2.1 Disparagement to Hobbes
Hobbes was criticized by many for his erroneous
inference regarding the object of one’s own will as merely thinking for one’s
fulfillment of the personal interests. He believed by focusing on the personal
interests that justice, peace, fraternity all those things are unintentional
emergence.[56] According to the critiques especially in the view of
Cumberland, he failed to recognize the selfless act which is directed towards
the good of the other.[57] Critiques emphasized the groundedness of morality in
human rational abilities instead of emotional outcomes.[58] What we should discover the laws of nature is the
birthplace of morality as rationality and not mere emotionality.[59] The views of Cumberland, Pufendorf, Wolff, and Kant
had paved the way for the emergence of this type of thought pattern. Together
with Cumberland, Pufendorf emphasized the necessity of social living by fulfilling
the common duties towards the others.[60] According to him, we all human beings have a common
kinship by which we desist ourselves from harming others, exchange mutual
assistance, and benevolence to the betterment either with loss or without loss
of our own priorities.[61] What they proposed was
other-centredness rather than self-centeredness.
1.2.2.2 New approach proposed by Christian
Wolff and Immanuel Kant
For Wolff, duty towards others has the same significance
towards the duty towards oneself.[62] It depicts the Christian principle love others as
oneself. All human beings have an obligation towards the needy but it
should not endanger our own lives and restricted by the circumstances and
capacity. Our obligations towards our lives cannot be opposed by our
obligations towards the other.[63] According to
him, we all should owe the ethics of good Samaritan without having any failure
to fulfilling our responsibilities towards our lives.[64] Even though he insisted on the love towards the
needy, he claimed a need for unequal dispersal of this love too. ‘Works of love
are called benefits, and accordingly, friends strive to benefit us. Because we
are obligated to love all men like ourselves, we owe most love to those who
benefit us. The love of the benefactor is called gratitude, and so we should be
grateful to our benefactor’.[65] Duty towards the needy
becomes an ought only the need of the needy stronger than the need of
the giver. He says: in a
strict sense, each person is obligated by the law of nature to instantiate
perfection in his/her own life. Actions that tend toward perfection produce
pleasure and actions that tend toward imperfection produce displeasure or pain.[66] To fulfill the needs of
needy also are part of our way towards perfection.
As an attribute to Wolf’s
philosophical gesture, Kant developed his idea of universal practical
philosophy. What he tried was to discover the reason as the basis for morality
as opposed to other particularities. He spoke of the two kinds of rational knowledge: material knowledge, which concerns some
object, and formal knowledge, which pays no attention to differences between
objects and is concerned only with the form of understanding and reason, and
with the universal rules of thinking.[67] He did not look for the circumstances or
situations but for him, the moral law was a general formula in all situations.
He spoke of three natures of the moral law;
To consider an action moral, it must be done for the sake of
morality, ethical quality is defined based
on its motives not based on effects, to consider an act as ethical, it must be
taken out of our reverence to the moral law.[68] He called the fundamental moral universal principle
as the categorical imperative.[69] He avoided the dependence on the empirical activities
but the empirical gestures like feelings and desires are more common in today's
altruistic philosophies. His categorical imperative stands as objections to
treat other rational beings as mere means to our ends. That means rational
beings are ends in themselves and they are the subjects and makers of all laws.[70] To benefit the other is named as our moral duty. He
announced beneficence as categorical morality or universal principles which
bind all rational beings.[71] For him, since we are rational beings, we are
supposed to accept this universal principle; beneficence. Beneficence is
rational while mon-beneficence is irrational. The basis for our morality should
be freedom, it is giving the law to the will.[72] By accepting categorical imperative as a universal
principle, it respects the autonomy. Freedom of the will can never be evaluated
by experience, it is possible only by reason.[73] When Hume’s followers had emphasized sentiments, What Kant tried was only to give a prior role
to reason as the motive.
1.2.3 The new face of the philosophy of
altruism in the views of David Hume and Adam Smith
The love for one’s neighbor
of the Christian tradition encountered morals of sentiment on one hand and
morals of reason on the other hand in the advance of empiricism.
Non-metaphysical basis of the means-ends reasoning of Hobbes paved a way for
the better comprehension of morality which led to altruistic morality.[74] During this time, a new
thought pattern by emphasizing sentiments to make judgments of morality rather
than reason.[75] They believed that morality
should come out of feeling and emotions which showed a taste of altruistic
philosophy. David Hume’s views are debited to Locke, Berkley, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson. He believed
that sensation is the only way to know the world and the only basis to make
moral judgments.[76] When he made discussion
over the many forms of the virtues like sociability,
good-naturedness, humaneness, mercifulness, gratitude, friendliness,
generosity, and beneficence, he named beneficence with the clear meaning of
altruism as the uppermost worth that humanity can achieve.[77] This sympathy that developed through one’s own familial and social
relationships becomes a motivating factor to help the needy. For him, sympathy
was a principle to handover feelings to the other.[78] Emphasis given to emotion and
sentiment rather than reason gave a new face to the progress of the philosophy
of altruism.
At the same time, Adam Smith, the
contemporary of David Hume agreed to the egoism of Hobbes for the common good
and only with the egoism or with the freedom of oneself, one can advance in
their interest and have an economic gain and by which welfare of the society
can be protected.[79] According to Smith, the egoism of Hobbes are to be overemphasized. Our
natural prudence is to look after our interests. Since we are social beings,
we, human beings have sympathy or empathy towards others; we feel with the
distressed, the oppressed, and the happiness of the other people too because
morality germinates from our social beingness.[80] For him, the foundation of the moral sense is sympathy.[81] For him, sympathy is a passion for the other.[82] Here one tries to place one in the position of the needy through the
logic of mirroring.[83] The logic of mirroring does not
mean to act on imagination but to act on another’s perspective.
As we
have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can form no idea of how
they are affected, but by conceiving what we should feel in the like situation.
Though our brother is on the rack, as long as we are at our ease, our senses
will never inform us of what he suffers. They never did, and never can carry us
beyond our person, and it is by the imagination only that we can form any
conception of what are his sensations. Neither can that faculty help us to this
any other way, than by representing to us what would be our own, if we were in
his case? It is the impressions of our own senses only, not those of his, which
our imaginations copy. By the imagination, we place ourselves in his situation.[84]
Many had criticized him for its possibility of practicability only in
its proximity. But in reality, his principle of sympathy has a tone of the
self-sacrifice and its not more love for our neighbor but his principle is with
the involvement of reason-principle conscience and impartial observer
perspectives.[85] Rational groundedness of morality was least bothered in their
perspectives. For him, beneficence promotes social life by insisting on us to
double the happiness of our neighbor who is in need.[86] We can’t demand it from anyone but it can be appreciated by all.
Moderation of our passions and reining of our actions are done by self-command
or with a self-conscience.[87] Even though we could not find the use of the term altruism in their principles,
we could find benevolence and other-centeredness which had the tastiness of
altruism.
1.2.4 The modern sense of altruism in the religion of
humanity and social Darwinism
The modern meaning of altruism in the extreme sense began with Auguste
Comte who coined altruism into the history of philosophy with the gist of
benevolence and sympathy.[88] What Comte had tried through
this principle was the progress of social relationships instead of traditional
responsibilities towards God and the community. In his thoughts, morality
emerged by giving more importance to the interests of others than one’s
own. As I had mentioned earlier,
altruism originated from a specific part of the brain. As part of socialization, the presence of
altruism with the sense of sympathy was claimed even in all other sentient
beings too.[89] Ayn Rand presents altruism of Auguste Comte as follows;
Auguste Comte, the founder of
Positivism, the champion of science, advocated a “rational,” “scientific”
social system based on the total subjugation of the individual to the
collective, including a “Religion of Humanity” which substituted Society for
the Gods or gods who collect the blood of sacrificial victims. It is not
astonishing that Comte was the coiner of the term Altruism, which means: the
placing of others above self, of their interests above one’s own.[90]
Auguste Comte wanted to make a new religion of the great humanity or the
beings and defined it as Vivre pour autrui. Comte had defined altruism as follows;
The individual must subordinate
himself to an Existence outside himself in order to find in it the source of
his stability. And this condition cannot be effectually realized except under
the impulse of propensities prompting him to live for others. The being,
whether man or animal, who loves nothing outside himself, and really lives for
himself alone, is by that very fact condemned to spend his life in a miserable
alternation of ignoble torpor and uncontrolled excitement. The principal
feature of Progress in all living things is that the general consensus which we
have seen to be the essential attribute of vitality should become more perfect.
It follows that happiness and worth, as well in individuals as in societies,
depend on adequate ascendancy of the sympathetic instincts. Thus the expression,
Live for Others, is the simplest summary of the whole moral code of Positivism.[91]
For him, the altruistic principles control the family functions and even
the civic. The altruistic principles in the brain take the initiative to
regulate and weaken the egoistic principles even though egoistic principles are
necessary for their survival.[92] Since we are egoistic, it’s a difficult task. Thoughts developed by
Comte to support his views are complex. The sovereignty of our instinct to be
self-preservative or egoistic is forfeited to higher signs of progress of our
reason. For him, it generates a ‘fatal separation’ between heart and mind that
impends the unity of man.[93] If we try only to promote altruism by separating it from egoism it
would be a disastrous endeavor, unless it had stretched the mandatory phase of
advance.[94] If not, we can’t distinguish untainted altruism from altruism that
aided to encourage the self-centeredness of others.[95] Even though altruism takes its first step in family, the gradual expansion
of it happens with education and continued cooperation between intellect and
altruistic feelings which look for the renovation of the civilization of social
life by giving prior aptitude and attitude to the other-centered and
other-interested tendencies instead of self-centered acts with the view of
building up social affairs.[96] Comte calls it as follows; “the
ultimate systematization of human life must consist above all in the
development of altruism”.[97] When he proposed a religion of humanity, he proposed rejection of
individual rights if they are opposed to social duties and he wanted to train
everyone in altruism and what he did was the exaltation of the emotions over
the intellect.[98]
Ultimately, Comte thought, a spontaneous, natural, innate altruism[99] would come about, as human beings, through the evolution of thought,
were able to assert the superiority of intellect over emotion, and altruism
over egoism in their inclinations. This development is, according to Comte,
‘less easy to realize than the egotistical unity’, because of the effort
required by the intellect and is, therefore, once arrived at, ‘superior to
wealth and stability’[100] in making human social relationships secure. He called out for the
subordination of self-love to the needs of the others. According to him, it
protects both individuals and society. If altruism does not work in
collaboration with human rationality it won't get succeded. Mere rationality
may lead to one’s arrogance or vanity but with social responsibilities, it can
be used to do the best to the needy.[101] According to him, rationality
has to encounter the need of society and it makes the best discernment to do
them the best act.[102] For him, Evolved altruistic principles would guide the universal moral
principles.
Herbert’s interests in Social
Darwinism paved for his interests in altruism the same as Comte. By believing
in the theory of natural selection of Darwin, he said, in the evolutionary
process, altruism would be there in the evolution of the moral betterment of
human beings.[103] Even though his thoughts had the taste of Comte, he was not radical and
he even gave a prior emphasis to egoism above altruism. For him, the supremacy
of egoism above altruism is imperative and peremptory because, in a long life,
we give importance to ourselves than others.[104] His definition of altruism is simply an action that benefits others
than oneself.[105] What he preferred was a restricted egoism. According to him, clean
altruism or egoism is harmful to the world. The commitment to self-sacrifice, which
altruism involved, is incompatible with Spencer’s commitment to the survival of
the fittest in his evolutionary theory.[106] Altruism becomes outdated because the wants of the individual are most
entirely comprehended in a society where egocentricity accords with the
interests of all. It leads to taking pleasure in others’ cheerfulness.[107] What Spencer wanted to be a reconciliation of egoism and altruism in
the human evolutionary processes.
Nietzsche disparaged Spencer’s
social Darwinistic altruism by telling that he could not find any relation
between altruism and human development. What he could find is only an individual.
His critical approaches to morality are seen in his resentment thesis.[108] According to him, altruism can be another status of one’s psychological
weakness and he defined it as the most hypocritical form of egoism grounded in
resentment of others’ success.[109] For him, ones’ low worthiness is made use by the individual of altruism
to calculate the worth of others’ doings.[110] He criticized Spencer’s altruism because it removed the self at the
expense of an obsession with the other. For him, the reason for altruism has
lacked the experience of love.[111] Those who lack love, try to build an ideal world where they can
experience this love. For him, it is a pursuit of two loves of the unegoistic
ones who wish themselves to be emptied to serve their purposes.[112] For him, only because of pity, human beings think of others and do
something for the suffered.[113] Our acts to reduce others’ sufferings may be an insentient reproduction
of what our sufferings are. To relieve our pity we do good deeds.[114] He criticized everything that gave more importance to others than
oneself. Marx Scheler opposed Nietzsche's view by telling that one loves the
other not out of weakness but because of positive values.[115] Altruists end up fleeing from the fear of self and view themselves as
less worthy.[116] This is because, according to Scheler, altruism cannot answer the
question: why am I or why will I not be worthy of the positive value of love
from the other?[117] According to him, there is a place for the
value of reciprocity. Max Scheler spoke of two realms where one helps the needy; out of an expression of love motivated by a
powerful feeling of security, strength, and inner salvation, of the invincible
fullness of one’s own life and existence; out of certain modern alternatives
for love, ... nothing but the urge to turn away from oneself and to lose
oneself in other people’s business.[118] He continued to say, "love for the small, the poor,
the weak, and the oppressed is really disguised hatred, repressed envy, an
impulse to detract, etc., directed against the opposite phenomena: wealth,
strength, power, largesse”.[119] Through the evolutionary thoughts,
altruism began to give special concern for the animal behavior without considering
its motivations and to keep away from the self-sacrificial concern to merely
considering others’ concern as one’s own. By emphasizing either emotion or
reason as motives, much different
understanding of altruism developed throughout history.
1.3
Rationale and principles of the philosophy of altruism
Whenever we consider the philosophy
of altruism we should consider whether the action is motivated by reason or
emotion. Based on its motives we decide whether it's altruistic or not in moral
philosophy. Emotion is instinctive or intuitive feeling while reason means the power of the mind to think,
understand, and form judgments logically.
1.3.1 Categorical
imperative as the motive
In the understanding of duty, Kant
made the distinction between the "I want" (self-interest) and the "I ought" (ethics).[120] For him, ethical actions are not a spontaneous
one. When one is needed, therefore we look for some way to help the needy. An
act that comes out of duty can be named as two; actions that sprout out of the
sense of duty and action in conformity with duty.[121] Our actions towards the needy are
our duty towards the needy. When he spoke of the imperatives in the duties, he
spoke of hypothetical and categorical imperatives.[122] For him, hypothetical imperatives
with the nature of conditioned are guided by our self-interests or our desires
while categorical imperatives are with the nature of universality and unconditioned.[123] Kant made three formulations of the
categorical imperatives; the formula of universal law[124], formula of humanity[125] and formula of autonomy.[126] He explained four Kinds of Duties:
Duties Toward Oneself (Perfect: Self-Preservation, Imperfect: Self-Cultivation)
and Duties Toward Others (Perfect: Strict Obligation, Imperfect: Beneficence).[127] Actions without inclinations are
perfect and actions with inclinations are imperfect.[128] All his concepts of duties towards
others should be guided by reason.
According to Kant, motivated by
reason reflects the acceptance of categorical imperative as the binding force
of one’s action. When one acts according to this maxim, it becomes a universal
law.[129] A maxim is a pithy statement
expressing a general truth or rule of conduct. Without having a moral reason to
act, we should not make the action.[130] For him, rational knowledge is knowledge from principles or knowledge of the
particular in the universal or faculty of principles.[131]
Kant claims the duty of everyone to be beneficent. That means helping
others without hoping for personal gains. He portrayed a difference between
beneficence and benevolence too. He considered benevolence done from friendly leaning as unlimited whereas
beneficence from duty does not place unlimited demands on persons.[132] For him, beneficence is doing good
while benevolence as wishing good. Benevolence becomes beneficence in the
applied love of humans.[133] The beneficient concept is an
obligation for him. A benevolent individual receipts
gratification in the happiness of others and he defined beneficence as ‘the
maxim of making other’s happiness one’s end’.[134] His concept of beneficence gives his clear view of altruism. But the
limits our duties should hold are not clear in Kant’s view. He did not explain
how far our obligations should extend. According to one’s capacities, we should
fulfill our duty to be beneficent but we don’t have an unlimited duty to do it.
The reason should guide us to recognize what our obligations are. He also
argued for the impossibility of having universal non-beneficence as a law.[135]
Human beings are not meant for living in isolation. We are social beings
and we need support and help from each other and altruism can be claimed as the
best component for this human nature. Kant says we as human beings are always
in a psychological tension between seclusions and sociability.[136] When we are pushed into society, we look for seclusions or solitudes
and when we are in solitudes or seclusions, we look for sociability. Altruism
can be developed as a response to this psychological tension because human
beings are needy beings even though we prefer liberty from the other.[137] His concept of the duty of
beneficence has two characteristics; imperfect and meritorious.[138] By imperfect, Kant meant that there are no stringent positions to be
altruistic, some times certain other apprehensions may override the necessity
to be altruistic.[139] By meritorious, Kant meant that no one can blame ethically the one who
flops to do the act.[140] Our situations or our surroundings may influence how our altruistic
acts are. To make an act, we should make a choice. This choice should be done
only under reason. For him, the reason is not a mere theoretic gesture but a
practical indicative.[141] Even though emotions have a particular influence on our acts, reason as
motive overrides our wants and desires. In Kantian ethics, reason becomes the
motivator of our altruistic act. For him, altruistic acts are preferable
virtuous act but he did not support reason as a compelling motivator for the act.[142] For him, “reason necessarily makes
what belongs to mere appearance subordinate to the character of the thing in
itself”.[143] To have our lives in the world of non-beneficence, therefore, can be
named to make an act contrary to reason. His concept of duty of altruism should
stem from reason than mere immediate responses that emerged out of mere
emotions.
1.3.2 Sentiment as a motivating factor
As I had explained earlier, Adam
Smith and David Hume emphasized sentiment as a motivating factor to altruism. They
emphasized sympathy, empathy, compassion, tenderness, softheartedness as a motivating
factor for the altruistic acts. Hume takes the view that morality depends on
‘Some sense or feeling which nature has made universal in the whole species’.[144] As I presented, Kant did not accept
these views. He considered emotions as changeable, transitory and we can’t
depend on those emotions. Therefore, moral judgments needed abstractions from
emotion and feelings. For centuries, it was assumed
that all human behavior, including the helping of others, is egoistically
motivated. The term egoism refers to a motivational state in which the goal is
to increase one’s welfare as an end in itself.[145] Lawrence Blum criticized Kantian dependence only on
the reason for the altruistic acts. He says;
Specifically, Kant’s position as
consisting of three aims. First, according to Blum, Kant wishes to articulate a
single fundamental principle of morality that applies to all human beings –
this is his categorical imperative. Second, Kant believes that our common human
reason applied to moral knowledge must yield no internal tensions or
contradictions as otherwise, it would not give us a principled approach to
morality. Finally, Blum interprets Kant’s position as strict and categorical:
moral obligation is unconditionally binding, on all people, and at all times,
just because it is the right thing to do. These three aspects do not fit well
with how altruism or indeed morality is actually encountered in the world in
which we live.[146]
Sentiment as a motivating factor of
altruism always makes actions according to inclinations and desires.[147] Their inclination is to promote the
good of the other. It is egoistic too because here their inclination looks for
the wellbeing of the needy.[148] It means to feel for the other.
Affective perception or the cognitive imagination of the needy’s experience has
its place in emotions as a motivating factor of altruism. [149]By this motive, we enter into the
resonance with the other. We can have two types of resonances here; convergent
and divergent resonances. Convergent resonance means identical – I suffer when
you suffer.[150] Divergent resonance means reactive –
instead of showing the same feeling we keep a distance but at the same time we
show a particular concern.[151] By having emotion as the motive, one
feels an affinity with the suffered and one understands the difficulties of the
one who feels and thereby emerges sympathy, empathy, and compassion towards the
needy.[152] When one has emotion as the motive
for the altruism, one tries to know the
internal state of the person who suffers, generate emotional resonance, make a
neutral mimicry, try to intuit or project oneself into another’s situation,
imagine how another is thinking and feeling, imagine how one would think and
feel in other’s place, feel empathic distress and finally thereby emerge
empathic concern for the other.[153] This view assigns a sophisticated cognitive role to the altruistic emotions
through their capacity to recognize others as needy and to assess the nature of
their needs.[154] But I feel that it is hard to square these more reason-based roles with
the interpretation of emotions as instincts. The followers of this view say that there are many types of
goodness and why we should try to connect into a unitary principle. They believed that we do not need a reason as
the foundation that we need is the only sentiment as the motive.[155] The supporters of this view emphasized conduct
motived by one’s immediate emotional reactions to specific situations. For
them, altruism is a special type of emotion to help the downtrodden. They
believe that emotion as sufficient and necessary to engender an altruistic
motivation.[156] Both the followers of reason and emotion as the
motivating factor of altruism are so rigid to their views.
1.3.3
The principle of reciprocity
Reciprocity comes from the Latin word
reciprocus with the meaning going back and forth (retro-procus)
– giving and taking. [157]The actual meaning of it is a mutual
exchange and not logically equal to the notion of giving and take. It is a
standard of moral action with the characteristic of social interaction.[158] The foundation of reciprocity is
nothing but the thought that humans are social beings with the capacity to give
and take the benefits.[159] The ideal altruism emphasizes giving no anticipation of
future rewards while reciprocal altruism accentuates the giving with the
limited expectation of or potential for the expectation of future rewards.[160] Even though altruism impulses us to
benefit others, its nature is unconditional as holding a difference in itself
to reciprocity. When we think of helping the needy,
the principle of reciprocity prompts us to believe that, if their giving
is not returned, they are exploited. Thus echo on justice, equality, and
fairness of treatment instructs us to examine reciprocity as we consider
altruism.[161] Marx Scheler did not understand the meaning of the idea of reciprocity.[162] He believed only in the unconditional concepts of altruism. For
Nietzsche, altruism was an unacceptable
martyrdom [163]because by giving more importance to the needs of the other more than
ours can be called as a utopian view and it destroyed the giver itself.
Our traditions believe human beings still exist only because of
reciprocity. Our survival is only because of our ancestor's shared goods and
services on the web of obligation. It can be called a web of indebtedness with
an adaptive mechanism for the survival of society.[164] There can be positive and negative reciprocity too. Positive reciprocal
altruism is defined as the returning of the action with the same positive
effects one has given.[165] In the philosophy of altruism, negative reciprocity is defined as an attempt to get something for
nothing.[166] The golden rule concepts of our
ancient traditions go in hand with the principle of reciprocity with the
mutuality of our obligations. When Kant explained the principle of beneficence,
he emphasized reciprocation as its rationale.[167] Kant argues that one has a duty to be beneficent because it would be
irrational to forgo the possible help one might need from others in the future.[168] Kant emphasized the duty of mutual aid with human beings'
acknowledgment of their duties.[169] Regan emphasized the necessity of intensions behind our acts.[170] According to him, our helping and hurting depend on the alternatives
available to the decision making and if we do our acts only to get the rewards
its not reciprocal altruism.[171]Therefore he called for reciprocal fairness – one gets only something as
in the return of one’s fairness in the act and not merely with the motive of
rewards.[172] Scott says the philosophy of altruism may accept reciprocation even
though it does not demand it.[173] He spoke of two types of reciprocity in the philosophy of altruism.
First kind of reciprocity that
depends on conditions of reasonable exchange, and reciprocity that is by
contrast incidental to the giving act. In the first case, a company might, for
example, agree to give money to a charity as long as the charity puts the
company’s logo on all its future promotions as ‘free’ advertising which doubts
on the altruistic motivations of the company. With the second kind of
reciprocity, it would seem to be only fair that if a person has benefited from
another’s the selfless act of giving, they ought to do something in return,
regardless of whether it is expected of them.[174]
Reciprocation seems good in altruism but it is not demandable. Freedom
should be given to the one who receives help. Some times our indebtedness to
the giver may harm the voluntary nature of altruism. It is good to have a
reciprocal act with gratitude and kind but it should not be made as obligatory.
For the survival of humans, the principle of reciprocity should be appreciated
in the philosophy of altruism.
1.3.4 The principle of impartiality
Impartiality in the philosophy of altruism means to treat every being to
do justice to all on earth with equal respect and worth in unbiased and
unprejudiced with proper reasons.[175] R. Dworkin considers reasoning
impartially as a type of abstinence from our preferences and prejudices and to take
into consideration only the circumstances of the situation with the impartial
mind set up.[176] He made a distinction between equality in being treated and the
reception of the equal treatment. For him, being treated as a necessary
requisite for impartiality and reception of equal treatment is not as necessary
as being treated as an equal in the principle of impartiality.[177] He emphasized the adoption of priorities like a good reason for this.
The principle of impartiality in altruism can be called as seeing everything in
the viewpoint of God because God is impartial according to Christianity.[178] Buddhism even had called impartiality as one of the seven factors to
attain enlightenment and one of the four sublime status for the rebirth.[179] For Hinduism, it is one of the thirteen kinds of truth.[180] To do justice to the world or to the needy, impartiality claimes to be
an essential factor.
According to Brad Hooker, there are three points to calculate moral
impartiality. “First, one may ask
whether moral rules are being impartially applied. Second, impartial
benevolence may be used as a direct guide to practical decisions. And third,
the content of first-order moral rules may be assessed from an impartial
standpoint”.[181] The universal applicable principles
of Kantian deontological theories by placing rationality to the universal point
of view and by treating human beings as ends in itself instead of means
supported the impartial moral reasoning.[182] The principle of impartiality counts
the interests of all equally and even personal sacrifices can be made for the
fulfillment of overall interest satisfaction and maximization.[183] Peter Singer with a negative
consequentialist mentality spoke much of impartiality with the concept of
relatedness and nearness[184] that I will explain in the coming chapter. The impartialists either deny the existence of
morally admirable partiality or holds impartiality as a pervasive universal
requirement of morality. The principle of impartiality is constructed through
the ideal observer[185] too which portrays an agent or
person to make moral judgments without being influenced by any biased or
prejudiced mind to see everything from a particular point of view but this view
was criticized because of the observer’s distant from the actual situation. The
ideal observer was considered as the one who makes the proper judgment or one
who always does the right.[186] To do all our acts with impartiality
is always a question. When we choose to aid our family members and dear ones,
impartiality becomes always doubtful. To answer this question we may have to
see everything from the impersonal point of view that means seeing everyone as
persons. Our near ones and dear ones also will be considered as persons with
equal truthfulness with others.[187] There is another way of seeing it by
looking into the classification of moral principles as first-order moral
principles and second-order moral principles. According to this distinction,
impartiality belongs only to the second-order morality.[188] First order-morality always includes
ordinary choices or decisions with certain partiality. It also may give space
for the interests of the near and dear ones.[189] Second-order principles should be
always in accordance with the principles of justice and institutional rules.[190] But this type of moral action may be
a coercive morality.
We can define therefore impartiality in the
philosophy of altruism as follows; “impartiality, as an obligation of justice, may be said
to mean, being exclusively influenced by the considerations which it is
supposed ought to influence the particular case in hand, and resisting the
solicitation of any motives which prompt to conduct different from what those
considerations would dictate”.[191] With the ideal observative point of view and impersonal point of view,
the principle of impartiality has its own significance in the philosophy of
altruism.
1.3.5 The principle of
supererogation
Supererogatory acts are those beyond the call of duty or beyond what is morally
required of us and actions which go the extra mile and are praiseworthy on just
that account.[192] The word supererogation comes from the Latin word “supererogatio with the meaning of payment beyond
what is needed or asked. This emerges from super "beyond"
and erogare "to pay out, expend", itself from ex "out"
and rogare "to ask". It is the performance of more
than is asked for; the action of doing more than duty requires”.[193] It means to
know how much one is obliged to do and go beyond it. Here the oughtness includes
a can. The failure of these supererogatory acts is not blamed. In the
catholic tradition, supererogatory acts are considered as a gesture for
individual salvation and salvation of others. Thomas Aquinas spoke of the two
merits of the principle of supererogation. On the one hand, supererogation serves as a more expedient or
guaranteed way of achieving everlasting life; on the other, it is intrinsically
good in being aimed at higher ends than the mere fulfillment of the
commandments.[194] He gave importance to the morality of
love than strict laws. [195]He did not make any difference
between duty and supererogation. Therefore it may obtain a meaning beyond the
line of law. The doers of supererogation are called as saints and heroes. Urmson defined supererogation as “actions that
are morally praiseworthy, valuable, although not obligatory in the sense that
their omission is not blameworthy”.[196]This definition tells us that it is
not morally required but good to have it. We are under no moral obligation to
do such acts but it’s an act of Good Samaritan – give what is necessary to the
needy. This principle of supererogation goes beyond duty and doing good as much
as possible.
There are three views related to
supererogation. The first of them is Anti-supererogation. It argues for
the obligations of the morally good action and the wrongness of its omission.
According to anti-supererogation, there exists a “good-ought tie-up”.[197] Doing best is always obligatory and
it can never be optional. Therefore, supererogation is impossible for them.
Even though Kantian beneficence spoke of the unwantedness of unnecessary blames
to the one who does not do the supererogatory act, his concept has a negative
tone to supererogation too.[198] ‘Kantian ethics is based on the
general idea of an all-encompassing moral law and conceives of duty as the
only expression of moral value in human action. Universalizability of the maxim
of action and acting from the sense of duty (or respect for the law) as a
motive are two constitutive hallmarks of moral action according to Kant. But
the two are incompatible with the nature of supererogatory action, which is
optional and personal on the one hand and not motivated by the subjection to
the moral law on the other’.[199] Classical utilitarianism also denied
supererogation because the fundamental end of every action is to promote the
overall good. It should be an obligation and should not be optional.
The second one is the Qualified
supererogation. It emphasizes the fact that “there are actions which lie
beyond the call of duty, but their value is derived from their being
hypothetical duties, subjective duties, duties from which one may be excused,
that is, duties in a weaker sense”.[200] They considered supererogation as
moral action with qualified sense and as a moral requirement. But at the same
time, they believed it’s not meant for all because they try to use the
principle of excuse.[201] In this concept, they talk of
supererogation with the reason for action.[202] Each action may have a reason and at
the same time, there will be the second-order reason not to act that one. This
permission may be named as exclusionary.[203] But this view failed to give what
actually meritorious supererogation is.
The third one is unqualified
supererogation.[204] This view underlines the fact that
supererogatory actions are without qualification beyond the requirements of
morality and that is the basis of their unique value. [205]The principle of supererogation is
called the higher flights of morality and morality of aspiration because of its
freedom, choice, beyondness of one’s responsibility ad obligations.[206]
Going beyond one’s duty points to the free choice. It means it's not
commanded, demanded and imposed. They believe supererogation as the best
because of liberty with which one performs. Since it is optional, for the omission of an act, one does not find
any excuse or doesn't need to get permission. Therefore supererogation is a
personal and spontaneous act with liberty.[207] The presence of supererogation in the
philosophy of altruism doubles its effectiveness and goodness in the world.
What I tried all through this chapter
was to present the basic understandings of the philosophy of altruism. Even the
philosophy of altruism seems like a simple, it's understandings ae somewhat
complex. Philosophy of altruism is a practical philosophy with the intention of
the betterment of others. The philosophy of altruism claims
itself to be an unconditional philosophy of love and kindness which provides
helps to all who are in need and achieve a type of satisfaction by helping
others and by promoting the interests of the other. Religious philosophies of
Christianity, Buddhism, Jainism, Judaism, Islam propagate the philosophy of
altruism through their concepts Golden Rule. Aristotle, Aquinas, Thomas Hobbes,
David Hume, Auguste Comte, Herbert Spencer, Adam Smith, Nietzsche, Kant, Marx Scheler, John Stuart Mill, Peter Singer
have their way of defining and proposing concepts related to altruism but they
all aim only one thing, the goodness of the other and the needy. Since we are
human beings, we all find a conflict between egoism and altruism. The principle
of impartiality, impersonality, reciprocity, supererogation call for the
betterment or wellbeing of the other in the philosophy of altruism. Even though
there are views regarding the motivations behind the moral act of altruism with
emotions and reason, they both emphasized the betterment of the other. The
otherness is respected very well in the philosophy of altruism. Whatever be the
motivations behind each altruistic acts, all prefer to reduce the suffering of
all. Philosophy of altruism shows a theorem with a pragma for the other even
with the self-emptying nature. Therefore, all the concepts, principles and
historical nurture of philosophy of altruism tell to the world, to be an
altruistic philosopher means to be selfless for the well-being of the other.
[1] Cf. A. COMTE, System of Positive Politics I (Paris2 1851) 680.
[2] Cf. ibid., 692.
[3] Cf. ibid., 694.
[4] The instincts are
sorted according to the dual rule of decreasing energy and increasing social
importance. For example, the first instinct, the instinct of nutrition, is the
most energetic one, since nutrition is an absolute necessity, but it is less important
in term of morality; the opposite applies to kindness or the love of humanity,
the tenth instinct, which is morally the most important, but the least
energetic. Comte sorts these ten instincts into three categories. Five
instincts (nutrition, sex, maternal, military or destructive, and industrial or
constructive) make up interest or pure egoism; then two intermediate tendencies
(domination and approbation) are egoistic, but require social relations in
order to satisfy the human drive toward ambition; and, finally, there come
three pure altruistic instincts (attachment, veneration and kindness).
[5] Cf.
ibid., 700.
[6] Ibid., 693. .
[7] Ibid., 694.
[8] Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism ( London
2016) 5.
[9] H. SPENCER, Data of Ethics (London
1879) 232.
[10] Cf. ibid., 233.
[11] Cf. ibid., 235.
[12] In the first
stage, one gets one’s share, or one’s share in respect of egoism; then
contracts bind those providing the various means; then market contracts are to
be respected – maintaining, through supply and demand, a due adjustment of the
advantages and the labour given, developing within industrial society. These
two intermediary stages entail the decline of direct and indirect aggression,
engendering the final stage, characterized by an increase of sympathy leading
to exchange of services beyond agreement.
[13] H. SPENCER, Data of Ethics, 276.
[14] Cf. ibid., 277.
[15] Cf. ibid., 278.
[16] Cf. T. NAGEL, The Possibility of Altruism
( Princeton 1978) 79.
[17] Cf. S. G. POST, Unlimited Love: Altruism,
Compassion and Service (Oxford
2003) vi.
[18] Cf. C. D. BASTON, Altruism in Humans (Oxford
2011) 21.
[19] Cf. K. R. MONROE, The Heart of Altruism:
Perceptions of Common Humanity ( Cambridge 1996) 6.
[20] Cf. ibid., 7.
[21] Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 19.
[22] Cf. C. D. BASTON, Altruism in Humans, 22.
[23] Cf. Ibid., 26.
[24]
Cf. F. HUTCHESON, An Essay on
the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, With Illustrations on
the Moral Sense (Oxford 2007) 207.
[25] K.R.MONROE, The Heart of Altruism:
Perceptions of a Common Humanity,19.
[26]
Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 21.
[27] Cf.
ibid., 22.
[28] Cf.
ibid., 24.
[29]
Cf. ARISTOTLE, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. J. A. K.THOMPSON
(London3 1976) 1155b-24.
[30]
Cf.ibid.
[31]
Cf. ibid., 1166b-30.
[32]
Cf. ibid., 1158a-10.
[33]
Cf. M. PAKALUK, “Friendship”, in: Blackwell Companion of
Philosophy, A Companion of Aristotle,
ed. G. ANAGNOSSTOPOLOUS (London 2009) 135.
[34]
Cf. ibid., 136.
[35] Cf.
ARISTOTLE, Eudemian Ethics, trans. M. WOODS (Oxfrod3 2005)
1217a-1218b.
[36]
N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism (New York 2007) 6.
[37]
Cf. Leviticus, 19,18; Tobit 4,15; Sirach 31,15.
[38] Cf.
Exodus, 20, 16-17.
[39] Talmud,
Shabbat 31a.
[40] Mathew
7, 12; Luke 6, 31
[41] John
15, 12-13.
[42] Mahābhārata
Shānti-Parva 167:9
[43] The collected oral and written accounts of Muhammad
and his teachings during his lifetime.
[44] E. HOMERIN, “Kitab al-Kafi”, in: NEUSNER AND JACOB(eds.), The Golden
Rule: The Ethics of Reciprocity in World Religions ( London 2008) 146.
[45]
Cf. H. J. GENSLER, Ethics and the Golden Rule (London 2013)
84.
[46] Cf. T.
AQUINAS, Summa Theologica II-II, q. 25, a. 5, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (Texas2
1981) 4473.
[47]
Cf. ibid., q. 25, a. 6, 4474.
[48] N.
SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 10.
[49] Cf. T.
AQUINAS, Summa Theologica II-II, q. 65, a. 2, 5035.
[50] Cf.
C. W. MARIS, Critique of the Emphiricist Explanation of Morality (London 1961) 24-25.
[51]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 12.
[52]
Cf. ibid., 13.
[53] Cf. T. HOBBES, Leviathan, trans. R. HAY
(London2 1651) 88.
[54]
Cf. ibid., 90.
[55]
Cf. ibid., 91.
[56] Cf.
C.W. MARIS, Critique of the
Empiricist Explanation of Morality, 28.
[57]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 14.
[58]
Cf. R. CUMBERLAND, A
Treatise of the Laws of Nature (Indiana 2013) 399-402.
[59]
Cf. ibid., 403.
[60]
Cf. S. PUFENDORF, On the Duty of Man and Citizen According to
Natural Law,trans. J.
TULLYED - M. SILVERTHOME (Cambridge 1991) 234.
[61]
Cf. ibid., 235.
[62] Cf. G. GAVA, “Kant, Wolff, and the Method of Philosophy”, in: D. GARBER - D. RUTHERFORD(eds.), Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy,
Volume VIII (Oxford 2018) 272. These
views are actually referred to Philosophia Practica Universalis of
Christain Wolff.
[63]
Cf. Ibid., 274.
[64]
Cf. ibid., 275.
[65] Cf. ibid.
[66]
Cf.ibid., 278.
[67]
Cf. I. Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. J. BENNETT
(London2 2017) 1.
[68]
Cf. ibid., 4.
[69]
Cf. ibid., 14.
[70]
Cf. ibid., 18.
[71]
Cf. ibid., 23.
[72]
Cf. ibid., 31.
[73]
Cf. ibid., 44.
[74] Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 15.
[75]
Cf. ibid., 16.
[76]
Cf. D. HUME, A Treatise on Human Nature , ed. L.A. SELBY BIGGE (Oxford2 1896) 240.
[77]
Cf. ibid., 243.
[78]
Cf. ibid., 245.
[79]
Cf. A. SMITH, The Theory of Moral Sentiments , ed. J. BENNETT (London2 2017) 2.
[80]
Cf. ibid., 3.
[81]
Cf. ibid.
[82]
Cf. ibid., 10.
[83]
Cf. ibid., 12.
[84] Ibid., 15.
[85]
Cf. ibid., 16.
[86]
Cf. ibid., 30.
[87]
Cf. ibid., 35.
[88] Cf.
A. COMTE, System of Positive
Politics I, 698.
[89]
Cf. ibid., 700.
[90] R. L. CAMPBELL, “Altruism in Auguste
Comte and Ayn Rand”: The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7, no. 2 (Spring
2006) 359.
[91] A. COMTE, System of Positive Politics
I, 565-566.
[92]
Cf. ibid., 701.
[93]
Cf.ibid.,704.
[94]
Cf. ibid., 705.
[95]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 17.
[96] Cf.
ibid., 18.
[97] A. COMTE, System of Positive Politics
IV, 253.
[98]
Cf. ibid., 254.
[99]
Cf. A. COMTE, System of Positive Politics III, 589 .
[100]
A. COMTE, Cathechisme Positive I
(Paris2 1853) 204.
[101]
Cf. Ibid., 205.
[102]
Cf. ibid., 208.
[103]
Cf. H. SPENCER, Data of Ethics,
169.
[104]
Cf. ibid., 181.
[105]
Cf. ibid., 185.
[106]
Cf. ibid., 188.
[107]
Cf. Ibid., 200.
[108]
Cf. F. NIETZSCHE, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. C.
DIETHEW (Cambridge2 2006) 18.
[109]
Cf. ibid., 64.
[110] Cf. ibid., 66.
[111]
Cf. F. NIETZCHE, Daybreak: Thoughts on the prejudies of
morality, trans. R. J.
HOLLINGDALE (Cambridge2 1982) 147.
[112]
Cf. ibid., 148.
[113]
Cf. ibid., 149.
[114]
Cf. ibid., 150.
[115] Cf. M. Scheler, Ressentiment , trans. L. A. COSER (Cambridge2 1971) 88-89.
[116]
Cf., ibid.,94-95.
[117]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 20.
[118]
Cf. M. Scheler, Ressentiment, 95.
[119]
Ibid., 96.
[120]
Cf. I. Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, 4.
[121]
Cf. ibid., 19.
[122]
Cf. ibid.
[123]
Cf. ibid.
[124]
Act as if the maxim of your actions were to secure through your will a
universal law of nature. Cf. ibid., 30.
[125]
Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or that of another,
always as an end and never as means only. In essence, every person has
intrinsic valueand the humanity is a limit or constraint on our action. Cf. ibid.,
32.
[126]
Every rational being must act as if he were through his maxim always a
legislating member in the universal kingdom of ends. In other words , we have
to will what is consistent with the operations of the kingdom as a whole. In
sum, both persons should consider themselves as both members and heads. Cf. ibid.,
36.
[127]
Cf. ibid., 21.
[128]
Cf. ibid., 23.
[129]
Cf. ibid.
[130]
Cf. ibid., 25.
[131]
Cf. ibid.
[132]
Cf. ibid., 27.
[133]
Cf. ibid., 28.
[134]
Cf. ibid., 31.
[135]
Cf. ibid., 33.
[136]
Cf. ibid., 41.
[137]
Cf. ibid., 43.
[138]
Cf. ibid., 44.
[139]
Cf. ibid., 46.
[140]
Cf. ibid., 47.
[141]
Cf. ibid.
[142]
Cf. ibid., 48.
[143]
Cf. ibid., 51.
[144]
Cf. D. HUME, Inquiries Concerning
Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals (Oxford2
1975) 173.
[145]
Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 45.
[146]
L. BLUM, Friendship, Altruism
and Morality (London 1980) 87
[147]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 22.
[148]
Cf. ibid., 25.
[149]
Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 46.
[150]
Cf ibid.
[151]
Cf .ibid., 47.
[152]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 25.
[153]
Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 47.
[154]
Cf .ibid., 48.
[155]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 25.
[156]
Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 47.
[157]
Cf. M. RIDLEY, The Origins of
Virtue (London 1997) 55.
[158]
Cf. ibid., 57.
[159]
Cf. R. B. CAIALDINI - M.
SCHALLER, "Empathy-based helping: Is
it selflessly or selfishly motivated?": Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology (1987) 52 (4): 751.
[160]
Cf. ibid., 754.
[161]
Cf. M. RIDLEY, The Origins of Virtue,
61.
[162]
Cf. M. Scheler, Ressentiment, 90.
[163]
Cf. F. NIETZCHE, Daybreak:
Thoughts on the Prejudies of Morality, 148.
[164]
Cf. M. RIDLEY, The Orgins of
Virtue, 59.
[165]
Cf. M. RICARD, Atruism, 55.
[166]
Cf. ibid
[167]
Cf. I. Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, 58.
[168]
Cf. ibid., 61.
[169]
Cf. ibid., 65.
[170]
Cf. D.T. REGAN, "Effects of a favor and liking on
compliance": Journal of Experimental Social Psychology (1971)
7 (6): 627.
[171]
Cf. ibid., 629.
[172]
Cf. ibid., 630.
[173]
Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 44.
[174]
Cf. ibid.
[175]
Cf. J. KEKES, “Morality and Impartiality,”: American Philosophical Quarterly (1981) 18: 295.
[176]
Cf. R. DWORKIN, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge 1977) 45.
[177]
Cf. ibid., 50.
[178]
Cf. Romans 2:11
[179]
Cf. N. MAHATHERA, The Buddha
and His Teachings (Taiwan 1998) 69.
[180]
Cf. Mahabharata, Santi Parva, 56: 2.
[181]
B. HOOKER, “When is Impartiality Morally Appropriate?”: Feltham and Cottingham (2010) 26.
[182]
Cf. I. Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, 33.
[183]
Cf. J. DANCY, Ethics without Principles (Oxford 2004) 78.
[184]
Cf. P. SINGER, “Famine, Affluence,
and Morality”: Philosophy and Public
Affairs, Vol. 1, No. 3 (1972) 229-243.
[185]
Cf. R. M. HARE, Moral Thinking
(Oxford2 1981) 111.
[186]
Cf. ibid., 112.
[187]
Cf. Cf. N. SCOTT - J. SEGLOW, Altruism, 51.
[188]
Cf. B. BARRY, Justice as Impartiality (Oxford 1995) 133.
[189]
Cf. ibid.
[190]
Cf. ibid.
[191]
Cf. J.S. MILL, Utilitarianism
(London2 1863) 44.
[192]
Cf. D. MAUZUTIS, “Supererogation Beyond Positive
Deviance and Corporate Social Responsibility”: Journal of Business Ethics (2014) 119: 517.
[193]
C. ALLEN, “Supererogation”, in: E. N. ZALTA – U. NODELMAN (eds.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Stanford 2017) 645.
[194] Cf. T. AQUINAS, Summa Theologica II-II,
q.106, a.4, 448.
[195]
Cf. Ibid.
[196]
J. URMSON, “Saints and Heroes”, in: Essays in
Moral Philosophy, ed. A. MELDEN (Seattle 1958) 234.
[197]
Cf. C. ALLEN, “Supererogation”, in: E. N. ZALTA – U. NODELMAN (eds.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , 646.
[198]
Cf. T. HILL, “Kant on Imperfect Duty and Supererogation”: Kant-Studien, 62: 58. .
[199]
Cf. ibid., 61.
[200]
Cf. C. ALLEN, “Supererogation”, in: E. N. ZALTA – U. NODELMAN (eds.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , 649.
[201]
Cf.ibid., 650.
[202]
Cf. ibid., 652.
[203]
Cf. ibid., 663.
[204]
Cf. ibid., 670.
[205]
Cf. ibid., 671.
[206]
Cf. J. URMSON, “Saints and Heroes”, in: Essays in Moral Philosophy, ed. A. MELDEN, 236.
[207]
Cf. ibid., 237.
Comments
Post a Comment